Karl Polanyi (1886-1964), was a Hungarian lawyer, economic
historian, and by some measures an economic anthropologist. He is considered to be the first original
theoretician within the field of economic anthropology (Sarkany 1990:186) as “virtually
all present-day anthropological analyses of prehistoric or non-Westem economies
that self-consciously avoid imposing market (capitalist or microeconomic)
concepts and categories are carrying on the Polanyi tradition” and some of his “most
basic concepts, especially reciprocity and redistribution, have become
anthropological stock in trade” (Isaac
2005:22). His influence stretches beyond anthropology as well, as his
book The Great Transformation (1944) “remains the most powerful indictment of what he
considered to be the utopian and ultimately destructive attempt to build society
on the basis of self-regulating markets” (Hart and Hann 2009:1).
His main contributions
were his theories of the “embedded” nature of the economy within society, and
of the “double movement” when capitalist logic separated the economy from
society in the 19th and early 20th centuries, and then
(partially) reembedded it through countermeasures that created social welfare
and state socialist societal models in the 20th century (Isaac 2005:14-15). Another contribution of his was “a flexible theoretical
framework” that afforded the opportunity to include non-capitalist; tribal,
kinship, and reciprocity based societies in economic analysis as they were exposed
to the effects of the market economy (Sarkany 1990:186). In short, he included
a multitude of societies in his work, and saw society and the economy as a
social whole – in which one could not see or study one aspect of it (e.g. the
economy) as a separate institution devoid of influence from other parts of
society.
He saw the economy as an “instituted process of interaction
between man and his environment, which results in a continuous supply of want
satisfying material means” (Polanyi 1957:248). This meant the economy was
always in motion, but also contained institutions were this constant movement
was concentrated (Polanyi 1957:248-9). These institutions, processes, and in turn the economy “as a
rule, is submerged in his social relationships;” and thus “a mere function of
social organization” (Polanyi 2001 [1944]:48, 52). He labeled his notion of the economy as “the
human economy,” and believed it was “embedded and enmeshed in institutions,
economic and noneconomic” (Polanyi 1957:250). He believed that including the
noneconomic in economic analysis was vital, “for religion or government may be
as important for the structure and functioning of the economy as monetary
institutions or the availability of tools and machines themselves that lighten
the toil of labor” (Polanyi 1957:250). As such he thought individuals in tribal
societies were “motivated to act by the requirements of social status, and not
by individual material interests” (Sarkany 1990:183-4). Or, in Polanyi’s words:
“Custom and law, magic
and religion cooperated in inducing the individual to comply with rules of
behavior which, eventually, ensured his functioning in the economic system”
(Polanyi 2001 [1944]:57).
This concept is at odds with (neo)classical economist’s
interpretations of economic society. But to Polanyi, reciprocity and
redistribution were as important to an economy as marketplace exchange as “these
forms of behaviour were tied to the existence of determined social structures”
(Sarkany 1990:184-5). He also recognized that markets and barter “coexisted
with reciprocity, redistribution, and householding,” and which he believed were
the “primary principles of economic behavior’’ (Polanyi 2001 [1944]:59; Hart and Hann 2009:3).
Key to this analysis,
and the heart of the Great Transformation is his analysis of the emergence of
capitalism and the “self-regulating market.” The great transformation described
the rise of market society as new to human history, even a “radical break” from
previous societies (Hart and Hann 2009:5, Polanyi 1957:256). While there had always
been markets (or marketplaces) for exchange, the market as a way to
self-regulate all of society using supply-and-demand market
economies and capitalists modes
of labor and production was new (Isaac 2005:14, Hart and Hann 2009:2). “Price-making markets… were to all
accounts non-existent before the first millennium of antiquity, and then only
to be eclipsed by other forms of integration” (Polanyi 1957:257).
“In short, the mere presence of marketplaces does not necessarily signal a market (capitalist) economy, nor does the mere presence of money. Many pre or non-capitalist economies had ‘moneystuff’, but it was special-purpose money, rather than the general-purpose money that serves as a uniform standard throughout market economies” (Isaac 2005:16).
Throughout human history, markets had generally been a
subservient part of economic interaction, secondary to kinship, religious, and
other social relations in economic matters, and subject to regulation by the
agents of dominant social institutions (Isaac 2005:14; Hart and Hann 2009:2; Polanyi 1957, 2001). As such, the capitalist market economy was
seen as just one of many possible economies (Sarkany 1990:184).
“The whole of history apart from those last centuries, had economies the organization of which differed from anything assumed by the economist. And the difference, we now begin to infer, can be reduced to one single point—they possessed no system of pricemaking markets.” (Polanyi 1957:241)
He believed that price-making markets were an institutional
setup which were never “created by mere random acts of exchange” on a personal
level (Polanyi 1957:251). This was new with capitalist society as while “all
economies have mechanisms of distribution… only market (capitalist) economies
are integrated (primarily) through ‘exchange’ on price-setting markets (Isaac 2005:16). This countered mainstream neoclassical market logics that
claimed “market economy could be self-regulating as long as everything was
bought and sold without restriction” (Hart and Hann 2009:4-5).
In the Great Transformation he analyzed the emergence
and disastrous consequences of market capitalism, first in England and then in
the rest of the world. He saw a shift towards urban commerce that forced “vast new populations of wage
labourers” to rely on market mechanisms “for food, housing, and all their basic
needs,” within which “society itself seemed to retreat from view, being
replaced by an ‘economy’ characterized this time by market contracts instead of
domestic self-sufficiency” (Hart and Hann 2009:3). Polanyi criticized the
propensity to shift “nature, society, and humanity” into the market as “land,
money, and labor;” creating what he called “the fictitious commodities’’ that
included a newly marketized “human labor” (Hart and Hann 2009:4-6). “Political
power was used to ensure that capital was free to move where it wanted,” and
other principles of labor exploitation described by Marx and others became dominant
(Hart and Hann 2009:4-5). Old traditions that ensured material provisioning for
broad swaths of society faded away just as many “freedoms, such as the right to
work, were sacrificed in order to achieve this” (Hart and Hann 2009:4-5). To
Keith Hart and Chris Hann: “Unregulated markets are engines of inequality,” and
the notion of “markets as a natural force beyond social regulation” also served
to “legitimize wealth” and “make poverty seem deserved” (Hart and Hann 2009:3).
Within Polanyi’s view, “the tradition of the classical economists, who attempted to base
the law of the market on the alleged propensities of man in the state of nature,
was replaced by an abandonment of all interest in the cultures of “uncivilized”
man as irrelevant to an understanding of the problems of our age” (Polanyi 2001
[1944]:47). Or as Hart and Hann claim, people “play almost no part in the calculations of economists
and they find no particular reflection of themselves in the quantitative analyses
published by the media” (Hart and Hann 2009:10). Or in short, “the last two
centuries saw a universal experiment in impersonal society” (Hart and Hann
2009:10).
Polanyi also sought change through his analysis. He believed
that “modern societies should be built on the ancient mechanisms evolved for
managing distribution in primitive societies and agrarian civilizations, with
the market relegated to a supplementary and marginal role” (Hart and Hann
2009:5). He saw an opportunity to build such a society out of the rubble of
World War II, and was undoubtedly disappointed that his work was not headed to
a greater degree. Yet, with the advent of neoliberal deregulation, and “the
revival of market capitalism and dismantling of state provision[s],” their was
a possibility “for another round of disasters such as those Polanyi attributed
to reliance on ‘free’ markets for social organization,” and which offered the
possibility for political backlash and “a retreat from market fundamentalism” (Hart
and Hann 2009:9). Especially as the “absolute dominance of market logic” is now
more flawed than in recent decades (Hart and Hann 2009). As such, increased
interest in Polanyi's ideas is not surprising, especially as he “would probably
sympathize with all those currently seeking to develop new and more radical
forms of democracy” (Hart and Hann 2009:9).
No comments:
Post a Comment