In direct contravention to Marxian theories of capitalism are
those of (Neo)Classical Economics. This is a broad topical group and difficult
to summarize in such limited space due, especially due to the depth of its
infiltration into our lives and the seaming conflation of economics and
capitalism that pervades Western notions of economic life. Much of this
tradition starts with what Robert Heilbronner (1996) calls the “Commercial
Revolution” and centers on mercantile systems of trade and economic interaction.
During this time period (c. 17th C), an intellectual shift began as
Thomas Mun theorized money as more than a means of exchange (Heilbronner 1996:25).
Richard Cantillon also conceptualized “market driven society as constituting a
‘system’ with a spontaneous mechanism of self-adjustment and a coherent
relationship between the supply of money and the prosperity of the society as a
whole” (Heilbronner 1996:30), and a study of the economy became more
systematized and focused on the increasingly expansive commercial aspects of
society (Heilbronner 1996).
This intellectual foundation lay ground work for the rise of
classical economic theorists that began with the publication of Adam Smith’s Wealth of Nations in 1776, and who’s
theories were systematically tightened and expanded upon by David Ricardo in On the Principles of Political Economy and
Taxation in 1817. These two works became known as classical political
economy and “with many additions and changes, it dominated European thought
about economics from 1780 to 1880” (Wolff and Resnik 2012: 15).
Smith ultimately believed that for society as a whole to achieve
its greatest levels of economic and social success, there should no
interference in a “free market” for goods and services (Smith 1991:322). He
believed in the private ownership of property, and that each individual should
become an “expert in his own peculiar branch” of the economy or market, and
that through diversifying labor – and becoming experts – “more work is done
upon the whole, and the quantity of science is considerably increased” (Smith
1991:16). This was founded upon a belief that “the difference between the most
dissimilar characters, between a philosopher and a common street porter… seems
to arise not so much from nature as from habit, custom, and education,” and that
as each person acted in their own self-interest, developed their own niche and
differentiated themselves and their expertise from others, unique skillsets and
expertise would develop and help lift society as a whole (Smith 1991:20-1). In
other words, Smith believed that we were not born unequal per say, but through
education and diversifying our labor we created differentiation that he thought
was good for society and created a stimulating and competitive environment
“where every man may purchase whatever part of the produce of other men’s
talents he has occasion for” (Smith 1991: 23, 151).
Smith believed that “whatever part of his stock a man employs as
a capital, he always expects it to be replaced to him with a profit” (Smith 1991:272),
and that they should always work for more than they put in. This wage based
diversity of labor, with everyone industriously and competitively seeking to
create their own comparative advantage, would lead to ever more “revenue and
stock” and ever more demand for wage laborers. This pattern would ultimately
and continually lead to an increase in “the revenue and stock of every
country,” something that “cannot possibly increase without [this process]”
(Smith 1991:73). In other words, people innately seek growth and to profit from
their work, and this is the only way society and countries will develop. Yet,
in a departure from neoclassical and neoliberal principles Smith did not
believe in overworking people, he believed they’d be more productive without
being overworked (Smith 1991:86). He believed that the improvement of those “of
the lower ranks” (the majority of society) should not be seen as an
inconvenience to society, but rather an advantage, and that society can only
flourish if “the whole body of the people, should have such a share of the
produce of their own labour as to be themselves tolerably well fed, clothed,
and lodged” (Smith 1991:83).
What Smith and his adherents brought to “classical economics”
was a focus on production and larger macro levels of analysis. However, around
the time that Karl Marx published Capital
(1867), classical economics shifted towards more detailed “micro” level studies
of the economy that theoretically centered on the decision-making processes of
individuals and individual enterprises. This focus lasted through the 1930’s
and became labeled as neoclassical or micro-economics (Wolff and Resnik 2012:14-15).
These principles have seen a resurgence since the 1970’s and is based on the:
“claim that the result of individuals' self-interested buying, selling, working, saving, and so on, is, in effect, an economic utopia: a perfect economic harmony among all individuals and between them and nature. For this utopia to be achieved, according to neoclassical theory, society must (1) endow and protect each individual with the full freedom to act in his or her own self-interest and (2) establish the institutional framework (competitive markets and private property) that guarantees that freedom” (Wolff and Resnik:15).
By the 1930’s, this focus on deregulating markets and minimized
state intervention, led to a global economic crisis, and many people to
question both neoclassical economic theory and the very merits of capitalism
itself. In response to these crisis, John Maynard Keynes published The General Theory of Employment, Interest,
and Money in 1937. Keynes believed the chief reason for the collapse of the
economy was a huge drop in private spending which plunged the economy into
depression. He thought that the only way to be able to guard against the ups
and downs of the capitalist economy’s “business cycle” was to have the state
act to intervene in the economy in order to regulate lending, money supplies,
and the “macro” part of the economy on the whole. His overarching theory
“analyzes and presents (1) the rules and laws that give the economy its overall
structure and (2) the ways in which that structure essentially governs the
activities of producers, consumers, and other individual economic actors”
(Wolff and Resnik 2012:19). This prescription was very different from
(neo)classical economics which focused on individual human beings acting and
making decisions, and aimed to remove all structural hindrances to free
markets. Keynes believe that there were
economic structures surrounding us, governing us, and that we needed to
understand and control them with greater efficacy if we were to keep better
control of the ups and downs of capitalist cycles (Wolff and Resnik 2012:19).
While Keynesian ideas are often still turned to in times of
crisis (the recent Great Recession and its “bank bailouts”), starting in the
1970’s there was a very propitious decline in the favor of Keynesian principles
as neoclassical and (soon to be labeled) neoliberal economics began to increase
in popularity and eventually seemingly monopolize political debates (Harvey
1994). As we can see in Adam Smith’s work, the individual is the main actor in
a larger social structure. However, this
notion of the individual – central to any understanding of capitalism – was
expounded upon by both Friedrich Hayek and Ayn Rand in the 20th
century, and encapsulates the role of the rational individual in capitalist
life. In both of their works the individual is primary not just as an actor,
but as an ideological notion for the primary object and origins of any social
analysis. As Hayek states:
“there is no other way toward an understanding of social phenomena but through our understanding of individual actions directed toward other people and guided by their expected behavior. This argument is directed primarily against the properly collectivist theories of society which pretend to be able directly to comprehend social wholes like society, etc., as entities sui generis which exist independently of the individuals which compose them… It is the contention that, by tracing the combined effects of individual actions, we discover that many of the institutions on which human achievements rest have arisen and are functioning without a designing and directing mind” (Hayek 1948:6)
The logic that Hayek is espousing – and largely attributes to individualist
thinkers such as Adam Smith – is that we has human beings can only know so
much. We could never portend to understand or know everything about our
immediate surroundings, nevermind a larger society; nationally, globally, etc. He
believed that within this framework, and knowing what we know of ourselves and
those around us, we should act within our local knowledge sphere and do what we
can and know. Hayek saw the market as a perfect mechanism for individuals to
engage with a larger – incomprehensible – social society, and where we would be
treated equally; or more so, “be rewarded, not according to the goodness or
badness of his intentions, but solely on the basis of the value of the results
to others (Hayek 1948:21-22). In short, while the market may be harsh, it is equally
harsh to everyone that engages with it.
In terms of navigating the difficulties of the market, Ayn Rand
contradicts Hayek to some extent. While
she sees “the free market [as] a continuous process that cannot be held still,
an upward process that demands the best (the most rational) of every man and
rewards him accordingly” (Rand 1967:25), she also believed that “man’s most
valuable attribute [is] the creative mind” (Rand 1967:19). She sees the genius
of humans as the key aspect to our existence, and where as Hayek thinks our
intellect is limiting to its surroundings and that we should focus on the here
and the now, Rand see’s this genius as the foundation for rational thought –
what she considers the key to navigating the market successfully – and
seemingly not limited by locale or knowledge. The also differed slightly on the
emancipatory possibilities of the rational individual acting within the market.
While they both believed this individual freedom could afford opportunity for
all, Hayek also felt that “the preservation of individual freedom [was]
incompatible with a full satisfaction of our views of distributive justice”
(Hayek: 21-22). Yet regardless of their differences, they both see the individual
as primary and the market as the only pathway toward individual freedom,
regardless of possible outcomes.
Interesting information. I was previously not aware of this. I just entered to the Faculty of Economics. But I do not always have enough time to study all the material and do my homework. At first I was confused and did not know what to do, but then my friend from faculty, gave the cue about a possibility of help in this matter. He said if I do not have time for this, I can use https://www.assignmentexpert.com/economics help of assistants and you know what, it definitely helped to me. My academic progress has improved at some subjects. Those subjects that I did not understand before, these guys helped me cope with this!
ReplyDelete