Pages

Wednesday, December 30, 2015

Anarchism

Anarchism is an oft misunderstood social system, probably because it claims to not be a system at all! This of course is not true. Anarchism is a system of practiced social principles based on self-organization, voluntary association, mutual aid, and a rejection of authority as well as all forms of structural violence, inequality, and domination (Graeber 2004:3). Anarchism is about individual actors coming together in mutually beneficial communities and structuring their lives based on notions of self-autonomy, freedom (so long as not infringe upon another’s freedom), and caring for one another. It recognizes the individual as the primary actor, but places them inherently within a cooperative community environment not based solely on self-interest, but rather individual autonomy within communal interests. This differs from Adam Smith and Friedrich Hayek who viewed the individual actor – acting in their own self-interest, their own localized setting, using their own expertise, for their own good, as the foundation for a better society. The society of self-interested actor they depicted fostered competition between individual actors, while anarchism tries to create a cooperative environment for autonomous actors to work in cooperation with each other.  In (neo)classical and neoliberal ideology the state is used to provide the most fruitful and secure environment for the market to regulate society and foster individual entrepreneurship, anarchism in turn rejects the state outright as authoritative, exploitative, stifling, oppressive, violent, and utopian (Graeber 2004, Shannon et al. 2012, Kropotkin 1970). It is the state regulations and violence that pushes the agendas of the powerful on the less powerful.  In short, “the economic function of the state” is to “protect private property and the accumulation of capital” (Shannon et al. 2012:21). And in totality, anarchism is a set of ideas that happen to be inherently anti-capitalist (Shannon et al. 2012).

So what does capitalism look like to an anarchist, and why don’t we hear much about it? Firstly, anarchism – much like Polanyian thought – does not separate the economy from the rest of society, and sees “forms of domination presenting themselves in society without the need to root them in the economy” (Shannon et al. 2012:15). Anarchist  philosophy or prescriptions for society are less visible for numerous reasons, but one is that while Marxism tended to be “a theoretical or analytical discourse about revolutionary strategy,” anarchism tended to be “an ethical discourse about revolutionary practice” (Graeber 2004:6, my emphasis). While anarchism has roots globally and throughout human history, it is not a planned system, rather a practiced system of human interaction based on individuals taking initiative and acting in real time within a caring community of equals. this is however, not a prescribed utopian vision, but “since anarchism is a prefigurative practice, part of what makes an anarchist economics distinctly anarchist is a focus on alternatives and resistance enacted in the here and now” (Shannon et al. 2012:35).

This being said, Anarchism’s critique of capitalism largely centers on the wage labor system (as slavery), property (as theft), markets (as exclusionary), the state (as oppressive), and the system itself as inherently exploitative, hierarchical, and exclusionary. Within anarchist thought, the capitalist and the worker were only equal “from the point of juridical fiction,” as their economic situation – their “real situation” – proved to be amazingly unequal as the capitalist could survive the day without work if need be, while the worker could not (Bakunin 1871:7). If the capitalist thought the workers wanted too much money, s/he could wait a few days or find another place.  For the “terrible threat of starvation” hung over the worker and their family, and forced them “to accept any conditions imposed by the gainful calculations of the capitalist, the industrialist, the employer” (Bakunin 1871:8). Within this, the capitalist and property owners were afforded (actually guaranteed) by the state, the power and the right “to live without working” (Bakunin 1871:2; van der Walt and Schmidt 2009:50). This was seen as “a system of exploitation, which the anarchists evidently understood as the transfer of resources from a productive class to a dominant but unproductive one” (van der Walt and Schmidt 2009:50). After all, in terms of output, the capitalists did not actually physically produce anything themselves. Capitalism is therefore seen inherently to not reward the actual producers of the goods, rather to position these laborers as serfs or – even worse – as slaves. “Instead of people selling us or renting us out, we rent out ourselves. But it’s basically the same sort of arrangement [as slavery].” (Graeber 2004:70-71)
“If I offer my labor at the lowest price, if I consent to have you live off my labor, it is certainly not because of devotion or brotherly love for you… I do it because my family and I would starve to death if I did not work for an employer. Thus I am forced to sell you my labor at the lowest possible price, and I am forced to do it by the threat of hunger” (Bakunin 1871:2).
Or as Bakunin quotes a fictitious capitalist: “Know it well, I will pay you a salary as small, and impose on you a working day as long, working conditions as severe, as despotic, as harsh as possible; not from wickedness — not from a motive of hatred towards you, nor an intent to do you harm — but from the love of wealth and to get rich quick; because the less I pay you and the more you work, the more I will gain” (Bakunin 1871:7) communities of producers and consumers.” (Kropotkin 1970[1887]:169-170). In short, “all requisites for production must… become the common property of society, and be managed in common by the producers of wealth” (Kropotkin 1970[1887]:46). Property was of course part of the market, therefore inherently unequally distributed and obtained as the market was inherently unequal and biased towards “private rather than public outcomes” and “antithetical to anarchism” (Spannos 2012:55), as only those that had money were able to engage with market. 
“Under capitalism, goods and services were distributed through the market; they were commodities that had to be bought before they could be used. Access was conditional on the ability to pay, rather than on actual need. An unemployed person without a wage had no specific right to the goods or services one needed to survive, while the wages of the employed workers were at best just able to cover ones basic needs” (van der Walt and Schmidt 2009:51).
This process excluded many from obtaining the goods they needed to survive and excel. The ability to participate is the key factor which determines an anarchist styled economy (Buck 2009:68).  This is one of the main critiques of capitalism by anarchist practitioners and scholars; that “the capitalist structuring of life excludes participation from so much of human existence. Some workplaces are worker-managed, some are even worker-owned, but the communities in which such workplaces are located have no say over the values, processes, and results of the workplace itself” (Buck 2009:68). Capitalism as such is seen as a non-participatory economy in which countless people are marginalized, ostracized, or outright denied entry. This creates multiple hierarchies that interact with each other in dangerous ways – i.e. colonization, white racism, patriarchy, and capitalist modes of production – all acting together in debilitating ways (Volcano and Shannon 2012:89).

Anarchists generally employed (actually were equally involved in creating) Marxist class analysis (Shannon et. al. 2012:14). However, anarchist theory points to the possibility of three classes rather than just two. There was the working class – the producers (or those that were or will be) – which included workers, unemployed, pensioners, etc. The ruling class – the owners of power, people who controlled investment decisions, determined policy, etc – which was comprised of owners, top managers, large land owners, top state officials, politicians, etc. And a third class, often referred to as “the middle class,” “the coordinator class,” or the “techno-managerial class,” which highlights “the existence of people with a high degree of social power—often directly over working people—such as high paid lawyers, tenured professors at elite institutions, and so on.” This group is seen to have “material interests in opposition to the ruling class and the working class,” though are placed above workers in capitalist society due to their social power (Shannon et al. 2012:19-20). The “oppressive hierarchies,” “pervasive social injustices,” and exploitation inherent in the class issue “was uppermost in the minds of the anarchist movement” (van der Walt and Schmidt 2009:50). As such, anarchists “viewed class struggle as a necessary part of social change, and saw in the victims of class domination and exploitation—the working class and peasantry—[as] the agents of that change” (van der Walt and Schmidt 2009:51-2). Within this class system, the free market, private property, and wage-labor was nothing “but a means to exploitation,” that could “be put aside whenever it suited the ruling class.” To this accord, the ruling elite would publically imbue the rhetoric of ‘non-interference,' by the state in economic and regulatory affairs while simultaneously using the state to directly support, help, and protect their interests (the interests of the exploiters), and bolster their positions of power” (i.e. protecting private property) (van der Walt and Schmidt 2009:52). Capitalism to anarchists was seen as using the state as a tool for the ruling class, to the detriment of the working and coordinator classes.

This is the crux of anarchist thought, the state as a coercive, violent actor that limits individual autonomy and freedom. To anarchists, the role of the state within capitalist societies is clear: “the economic function of the state” is to “protect private property and the accumulation of capital.” (Shannon et al. 2012:21). These are things that obviously benefit the ruling classes, and most certainly act against the interests of the working class, as “the state is seen as a defender of the class system and a centralised body that necessarily concentrates power in the hands of the ruling classes; in both respects, it is the means through which a minority rules a majority” (van der Walt and Schmidt 2009:52). Hence the need for the state… 
“When a mother in search of food and shelter for her children must pass by shops filled with the most refined delicacies of refined gluttony; when gorgeous and insolent luxury is displayed side by side with the most execrable misery; when the dog and the horse of a rich man are far better cared for than millions of children whose mothers earn a pitiful salary in the pit or the manufactory; when each "modest" evening dress of a lady represents eight months, or one year of human labor; when enrichment at somebody else's expense is the avowed aim of the "upper classes," and no distinct boundary can be traced between honest and dishonest means of making money, then force is the only means for maintaining such a state of things. Then an army of policemen, judges, and hangmen becomes a necessary institution” (Kropotkin 1970[1887]:72).
Whether strong welfare, or a modern neoliberal, the state was designed to dictate social and economic terms (and structures) that affected individual and community capacities for self-determination. Capitalism and landlordism did not exist in some “invisible” vacuum, they relied on the state to enforce (or create) the optimum conditions for corporate rule and success. To Anarchists, capitalism could not exist without the state, if you wanted to abolish capitalism, and its inherent social inequality, you had to abolish the state. Or as Peter Kropotkin said: “The no-capitalist system implies the no-government system" (Kropotkin 1970[1887]:52).

While anarchism stresses that people can run their own affairs “without the need for experts or bureaucrats” (Shannon et al. 2012:13), it also differs from capitalism with an ideology that does not just focus on the self and self-autonomy, but on the individual’s place in society and communal life. Anarchists believe in mutual aid and a self-autonomy that does not willfully harm others. This tends to be the main distinction between anarchist autonomy and capitalist autonomy (or what some erroneously call “anarcho-capitalism”[1]); anarchism takes others into account and has “no legal possibility for coercive aggression against the person or the property of any individual” (Marshall 2012:561). This of course differs from the individualism of Rand and Hayek that posits that if one focuses on one’s self, acts in their own singular interests, and makes themselves the best they can be, that society as a larger whole will benefit – even if it may harm people within their direct contact in the shorter term. Again, calling upon Kropotikin:
“It is impossible to conceive a society in which the affairs of any one of its members would not concern many others members, if not all; still less a society in which a continual contact between its members would not have established an interest of every one towards all others, which would render it impossible to act without thinking of the effects which our actions may have on others” (Kropotkin 1970[1887]:173-4).



[1] see Marshall 2012:559-565

No comments:

Post a Comment